DO I LOSE THE RIGHT-TO-DIE

WHEN I LOSE CONSCIOUSNESS?


SYNOPSIS:

    One hundred years from now,
the right-to-die will be firmly established in all societies.
And this right-to-die will not disappear
when the individual passes over from being a full person
with all capacities to make medical decisions
to some lower level of decision-making ability.
At present, mental capacity is one of the dilemmas of the right-to-die:
One common safeguard requires that the person choosing death
remain fully capable of making the life-ending decision
up to the very last moment of life.
As we live longer and depend more
on life-support machinery at the end of life,
most of us will have serious limitations
to our thinking powers at the end of our lives.
But no matter how much mental decline we might suffer,
we should never lose the right-to-die.

OUTLINE:

1.   HOW "YOU MUST BE CONSCIOUS AND CAPABLE"
            CAUSES SOME PREMATURE DEATHS.

2.  THE REASONING BEHIND THIS SAFEGUARD.

3.  THIS DEATH SHOULD BE CALLED A MERCIFUL DEATH
            IF THE PROXIES ARE FOLLOWING THE PATIENT'S WISHES.

4.  WHEN THE WISHES OF THE DYING PERSON ARE CLEAR,
            SAFEGUARDS SHOULD NOT PREVENT CHOOSING DEATH.

5.  A PROBLEM IN THE NETHERLANDS:
            DEATH "WITHOUT EXPLICIT REQUEST".

6.  THE UNITED STATES HAS A STRONG ROLE FOR PROXIES.

7.  THUS, I DO NOT LOSE MY RIGHT-TO-DIE
            WHEN I LOSE CONSCIOUSNESS.

RESULT:

   
Some forms of the right-to-die require the individual choosing death
to be conscious and capable up to the last moment of life.
But it should be possible to affirm our right-to-die
in such ways that our plans for the end of life
will not be thwarted by any decline in our mental capacities.




DO I LOSE THE RIGHT-TO-DIE
WHEN I LOSE CONSCIOUSNESS?


by James Leonard Park

    Law and ethics now recognize the right of competent persons
to choose the time and means of their own deaths.
We might choose death by increasing pain-medication,
by inducing terminal coma, by withdrawing life-supports,
or by giving up water and all other fluids.
All of these are recognized legal ways of ending human life.

    Another on-line essay discusses these four ways in detail:
"Four Medical Methods of Managing Dying".


    Choosing death should not be done easily and quickly.
The more safeguard-
procedures we use,
the more fully we show that it was a wise voluntary death
rather than a foolish irrational suicide.

   
Here is another related essay,
which explores some useful safeguards for separating
voluntary death from irrational suicide:
Fifteen Safeguards for Life-Ending Decisions.
And here is an essay specifically separating
voluntary death from irrational suicide:
Will this Death be an "Irrational Suicide" or a "Voluntary Death"?


    One common safeguard suggested by advocates of the right-to-die
is to require the patient to be awake and capable of making decisions
at the final moment of life.
Those who advocate this must-be-conscious safeguard
believe this is the best way to make certain
that the decision for death was free and autonomous.

    For example, some right-to-die laws require the patient
physically to take the pills or push the button that will cause death.

    Under such provisions, the person who is
no longer capable of making a life-ending decision
or of taking the necessary action loses the right-to-die.
Is this safeguard wise and necessary?




1.  HOW "YOU MUST BE CONSCIOUS AND CAPABLE"

            CAUSES SOME PREMATURE DEATHS.


    All of us know that as we approach death from natural causes,
we often lose our abilities to make wise decisions
and to carry them forward
long before we actually die.
If we happen to be victims of Alzheimer's disease,
we can lose our capacities to make good decisions
literally years before we will die of natural causes.
Does it seem wise public policy
to deprive Alzheimer's victims of the right-to-die
merely because they have this particular brain disease
rather than cancer, for example?

    Some advocates of the right-to-die chose death prematurely
precisely because they feared losing the capacity to choose death.
They knew they were on the downward path.
But how many meaningful days of life might still be possible?
In order not to lose the right-to-die, they decided to take the pills now
rather than waiting until some time when it might be too late
to make the decision and physically to do the action themselves.

    The obvious way to prevent such premature deaths
is to allow proxies for the patient to carry forward the plan if and when
the patient can no longer express an opinion or take a life-ending action.
A well-constructed Advance Directive for Medical Care
should be sufficient to prove that the author wanted the right-to-die
when certain conditions of decline had occurred
—even if the patient was not conscious or capable at the last moment.

    This is what I have said in my own Advance Directive:
If and when I can no longer make my own life-ending decisions,
my proxies are fully authorized to make those choices for me.
See especially Question 6 in my Advance Directive linked just above.
They will follow my medical ethics in my Advance Directive.
And when I am no longer capable of choosing,
they will have the same powers I had
while I was still fully able to conduct my own life.

    There might be some problems with such a right-to-die provision.
But these can be resolved before the drawer of the Advance Directive
becomes unable to participate in further discussions
concerning just when and how his or her life should come to an end.  

    When an Advance Directive or similar document has been created,
when there is no doubt that the patient made these wishes known
at a time when he or she was still fully capable of making decisions,
then if and when the patient loses consciousness,
the right-to-die is not lost.
The right to made life-ending decisions merely shifts
to the duly-authorized proxies for the patient.
When I lose consciousness (either temporarily or permanently),
I do not lose my right-to-die
if I have fully and clearly claimed this right in my Advance Directive.

    It is quite ironic that some parts of the right-to-die movement
have insisted on this safeguard:
The you-must-be-conscious safeguard
forces some people to rush into premature death
rather than risk losing the right-to-die at a later time
when they lose the ability to make their own medical decisions,
including any decisions that will shorten the process of dying.
Advocates of the right-to-die
should not force patients to choose a premature death
because those patients fear losing the right-to-die
if they become incompetent or unconscious
before they exercise their right to choose a voluntary death.




2.  THE REASONING BEHIND THIS SAFEGUARD.

    Some advocates of the right-to-die take this safeguard
that you must be conscious and capable to choose death
as if it were a regulation handed down by God.
But actually this safeguard was created by people who were worried
that some individuals might be put to death by others
who did not have their best interests at heart.

    Thus, in order to protect the autonomy of the individual,
they require that the choice to end one's life
be affirmed several times before it can actually take place.
This wise safeguard prevents many irrational suicides
by people who have only a temporary urge to kill themselves,
perhaps based on a misapprehension of some medical facts
or because they have a distorted vision of their future prospects.

    However, careful safeguards could protect against irrational suicide
and against people being manipulated or coerced into 'choosing' death
by asking a number of independent people to review the decision.
If the facts lead several people to affirm death as the best choice,
then the chosen death should be carried forward
without regard to the mental status of the patient at the end of life.

    Several such safeguards are presented in another chapter:
"Fifteen Safeguards for Life-Ending Decisions".
Such safeguards make sure that the life-ending decision is wise
without requiring the patient to reaffirm the choice at the last moment.
When the patient becomes unconscious
or otherwise incapable of making any life-ending decisions,
then the proxies should follow the medical ethics of the patient
and make the life-ending decisions that the patient would have made
if the dying person were still fully able to carry forward the plans
explained in his or her Advance Directive for Medical Care.





3.  THIS DEATH SHOULD BE CALLED A "MERCIFUL DEATH"
            IF THE PROXIES ARE FOLLOWING THE PATIENT'S WISHES.


    Sometimes well-meaning relatives decide on their own
to end the life of someone they love who has 'suffered enough'.
This is commonly called a "mercy-killing".
And it should remain a crime
under any revision of our laws prohibiting causing premature death.
In brief, a mercy-killing is harmful, irrational, capricious, & regrettable.

    However, in contrast to mercy-killings, we need a new concept,
which might be called "merciful death".
A merciful death is carried out by someone other than the patient
because that patient has already lost the power to end his or her life.
But if the patient were still able to choose death,
it would be called a voluntary death, not an irrational suicide.
In short, a merciful death is helpful, rational, well-planned, & admirable.

  
  This distinction is worked out in full detail in another chapter:
Will this Death be a "Mercy-Killing" or a "Merciful Death"? .

    When all the proper and relevant safeguards are fulfilled,
then the proxies can carry forward the patient's plans
for achieving a timely death
not too soon and not too late.
If they follow the pathway towards death chosen by the patient,
then no harm has been done and no crime has been committed.
Helping someone you love to choose a timely death
can be an ultimate act of love.

    As this new concept of merciful death comes into fuller use,
doctors will know when to write "merciful death" on the death-certificate.
And the family will admire the patient's foresight in planning a good death
rather than merely waiting for natural death to occur.
The patient has specified in advance the conditions under which
death now is to be preferred over death later.
If the dying person were still conscious and capable,
he or she would take the necessary actions to achieve a voluntary death.

    I apply this to my own death:
If I lose consciousness before I die
and if I will never be able to make a life-ending decision,
then my proxies shall consult my Advance Directive
to see if the conditions for choosing death have been fulfilled.
If so, they shall carry forward my plans for death
just as I would have carried them forward myself if I were still able.




4. 
WHEN THE WISHES OF THE DYING PERSON ARE CLEAR,
            SAFEGUARDS SHOULD NOT PREVENT CHOOSING DEATH.


    Sometimes advocates of the right-to-die do not realize
that the requirement that the dying person must be conscious and capable
is really just one of several safeguards to prevent premature death.
And once they acknowledge the reasons behind this safeguard,
they will rationally be able to make exceptions
when the wishes of the patient are crystal clear.

    There might be better ways to honor patient autonomy
than to insist on full decision-making capacity at the last moment of life.
For example, a comprehensive Advance Directive
will specify the conditions under which the patient would choose death.
See Question 17Under what conditions would you request death?

    When the patient has lost the personal power to achieve death,
then the proxies are legally empowered to act for their patient.
The right-to-die does not disappear with consciousness.

    This is parallel to putting one's plans for assets into writing.
An estate will or trust does not become invalid
when the person who created that document becomes unconscious
or otherwise loses the capacity to make further financial decisions.
On the contrary, the reason for putting an estate plan into writing
is to make sure that the wishes of the drawer are fulfilled after death.
And if there is a long period of incapacity before death,
the executor or the trustee still has the power
to carry forward the plans as specified in writing.
Sometimes this is done by establishing a guardian or conservator,
who will handle the financial affairs of someone
who has lost the ability to make wise choices about money.

    A good Advance Directive gives similar powers to the proxies
so that they can make all necessary medical decisions for the patient
during any periods of time the patient cannot make medical choices.
In the case of Alzheimer's disease,
the period of proxies acting for the patient can be many years.
And if explicitly authorized in the Advance Directive,
the proxies can make life-ending decisions for their patient.




5.  A PROBLEM IN THE NETHERLANDS:
            DEATH "WITHOUT EXPLICIT REQUEST".


    Holland is one of the places on the planet Earth
where voluntary death has now become a legal and common practice.
Thousands of Hollanders take advantage of this right-to-die every year.
On average, they choose to die about one month
before they would have died of natural causes.

   
Thus these citizens of the Netherlands
might be said to be members of The One-Month-Less Club.

    One of the safeguards in the right-to-die law of the Netherlands
is that the patient must be conscious and capable to the last moment.
The patient must be willing and able to give informed consent
for the doctor to give the death pill or the lethal injection.

    But investigations have discovered
that a certain percentage of Dutch patients
have been put to death "without explicit request".
This means that the doctor helped them to die
even tho they did not or could not consent at the very last moment.
One report found 1,000 such cases.
However, what is not always reported along with this shocking number
is that most of these patients had previously requested assistance in dying.
And they had just waited too long to make the final request.
Some of them were unconscious
when the doctor gave them an injection to end their lives.

    This was a violation of Dutch law,
but no doctors have been prosecuted for this breach of law
probably because everyone can see that the right-to-die should not end
when the patient loses the power to participate in the life-ending decision.  

    Dutch law gives no explicit role for proxies to decide for their patients.
So the doctor must choose death on his or her own authority.  
If such a case ever were to come to court,
then the doctor would just bring forth all the documentary evidence
and the recollections of all the people who were present
to prove that death at this time was what the patient would have chosen.  

    Dutch law should be changed so that this common-sense extension
of the right-to-die is made explicit in the law and safeguards.  
From the perspective of how American medicine is practiced,
it would be reasonable to include proxy-decision-making:
When the patient can no longer make medical decisions,
then that power passes to another individual or group of persons
who were selected by the patient
while the patient was still able to make all medical decisions.




6.  THE UNITED STATES HAS A STRONG ROLE FOR PROXIES.
   
    It will not be such a radical revision for the United States
to extend the power of proxies to life-and-death decisions.
Most states already empower proxies to make medical decisions
when the patient no longer has the ability to make wise medical choices.
   
    This proxy-power is usually found in laws about Advance Directives.
But some states define durable power of attorney for health care.
This simply means that the named proxy or proxies have the power
to made medical decisions for the patient who appointed them
when the patient becomes incompetent or unable to make medical choices.  
   
    Some states have limited the power of proxies in particular areas
—such as the withdrawal of food and water.  
These states sometimes say that withdrawing such means of sustenance
cannot be chosen unless the patient has specifically given permission
for the proxies to withdraw food and water
as a means of bringing the patient's life to an end. 
Even in states whose laws do not address the question of food and water,
it would be wise to include explicit permission in one's Advance Directive.
Then there will be no uncertainty in anyone's mind
concerning whether or not this power was given to the proxies.  

    While we are still competent and capable ourselves,
we always do have the authority to give up eating and drinking,
with the clear recognition that this will bring our lives to an end.  
And if we live in one of the states with strong proxy laws
and if we have appointed effective proxies,
then our end-of-life decisions will be carried forward
as we have specified in our Advance Directives for Medical Care.  

    The following is what we mean by "strong proxy laws":
The state law authorizes the appointment of a person or persons
who will have as much power and authority to decide for the patient
as the patient has while fully able to make medical decisions.  
And when we write our Advance Directives,
we should specify that we do intend to give
all these decision-making powers to our named proxies.  
We might include an expression such as the following:

    "I hereby empower and authorize my proxies
to exercise all powers to make medical decisions for me
if and when I am no longer able to direct my medical care
or when I am unable to express my medical choices.
If I could make any specific medical decision
while I was still fully competent and capable,
then that full decision-making-power will rest with my proxies
if and when I cannot make my own medical decisions.
This authority explicitly extends
to the right to make all life-ending decisions for me,
including the withdrawal or withholding of food and water."

    In addition to making this explicit transfer of authority,
we should appoint some individual or group of individuals
who will assert this right even possibly against medical advice.
Because we ourselves always have the right to refuse any treatment,
so our proxies will also have the full right to refuse any medical care,
even if that refusal will inevitably lead to our deaths.

    When we can no longer make our own medical decisions,
our proxies will acquire our decision-making power
and make any end-of-life decisions for us
if we have explicitly given them this power in our Advance Directives
and if our state or country allows proxies to have this much power.




7.  THUS, I DO NOT LOSE MY RIGHT-TO-DIE
            WHEN I LOSE CONSCIOUSNESS.


    If I have carefully affirmed my right-to-die in my Advance Directive
and if I have appointed proxies who will carry my wishes forward,
then I do not lose the right-to-die
when I can no longer give informed consent.

    This will eliminate any temptation to kill myself prematurely
because I worry that I might lose my right-to-die at some later time.
I can allow myself to survive for more weeks and months
because I have the assurance that a wise life-ending decision
can still be taken by my proxies when the appropriate time comes.




Created November 9, 2006; revised 11-14-2006; 1-24-2008; 2-6-2009; 5-30-2009;
2-11-2010; 3-6-2011; 4-5-2011; 2-2-2012; 2-27-2012; 3-17-2012; 7-8-2012; 8-26-2012;
3-30-2013; 6-12-2013; 9-23-2013; 8-1-2014; 12-23-2014;
3-17-2015; 7-10-2015; 5-25-2016; 11-16-2017; 12-23-2019; 2-27-2020



AUTHOR:

    James Park advocates of the right-to-die with careful safeguards.
His own Advance Directive gives his Medical Care Decisions Committee
explicit powers to make all the medical decisions
he himself could make while he is still capable.
His proxies' powers come into effect
whenever he loses the ability to make wise medical decisions.
All of this is explained in great detail in his own
Advance Directive for Medical Care.

    Much more information about James Park will be found on his website:
James Leonard Park—Free Library




This discussion of keeping the power to choose death
even after one loses some mental abilities
  has become Chapter 36 of How to Die: Safeguards for Life-Ending Decisions:
"Do I Lose the Right-to-Die when I Lose Consciousness?"



Here are a few related chapters and essays:

Losing the Marks of Personhood:
Discussing Degrees of Mental Decline

Advance Directives for Medical Care:
24 Important Questions to Answer

Fifteen Safeguards for Life-Ending Decisions

Will this Death be an "Irrational Suicide" or a "Voluntary Death"?

Will this Death be a "Mercy-Killing" or a "Merciful Death"?

Four Medical Methods of Managing Dying

VDD:
Why Giving Up Water is Better than other Means of Voluntary Death

Voluntary Death by Dehydration:
Safeguards to Make Sure it is a Wise Choice

Depressed?
Don't Kill Yourself!




    Further Reading:


Best Books on Voluntary Death


Best Books on Preparing for Death


Books on Terminal Care



Books on Helping Patients to Die


Books Supporting the Right-to-Die


Books Opposing the Right-to-Die



Go to the Right-to-Die Portal.


Go to the Book Review Index
to discover more than 350 book reviews
organized into more than 60 bibliographies.


Return to the DEATH page.


Go to the Medical Ethics index page.


Go to on-line essays by James Park,
organized into 10 subject-areas.


Go to the beginning of this website
James Leonard Park—Free Library