Introduction

Suicide Prevention and the Right-to-Die

    Is this book another suicide manual?  NO.
In contrast to other books supporting the right-to-die,
every page of this book seeks to prevent irrational suicide.

    In the next 12 months, 30,000-40,000 Americans will kill themselves.
This will be a terrible loss of life,
both for the people who will throw their lives away
and for other people who know them and care about them.

    One feature that makes irrational suicide even more tragic
is that almost all of these needless deaths could be prevented.
If we foresee which people are most likely to attempt to kill themselves, 
we can probably take protective action to save them from themselves.

    The Americans who will kill themselves in the next 12 months
will make this 'decision' to end their lives for a variety of 'reasons'.
Some will commit irrational suicide because of problems with 'love'.
Some will commit irrational suicide because of financial disaster.
Some will commit irrational suicide to harm others.
Some will commit irrational suicide because of weird religious beliefs.
Some will commit irrational suicide due to internal conflicts.

    However, a few people who will choose death in the next 12 months
will have valid reasons to choose their own dates of death.

    Perhaps 90% of all self-killings should be classified as irrational suicide.
And perhaps 5% should be classified as voluntary death.
This leave another 5% between irrational suicide and voluntary death.

    Of course, these terms need to be carefully defined:
Irrational suicide is harmful, irrational, capricious, & regrettable.
Voluntary death is helpful, rational, well-planned, & admirable.
Chapter 19 of this book elaborates these distinctions:
Will this Death be an “Irrational Suicide” or a “Voluntary Death”?
And in a deep sense this whole book explores the safeguards
that will be the operational method for separating
regrettable irrational suicide from admirable voluntary death

    Irrational suicide can and should be prevented as much as possible.

    But voluntary death should become a more open and honest choice. 

    Careful thought can combine suicide prevention and the right-to-die.



    Forms of the right-to-die can be arranged along a spectrum:
At one extreme is the suicide-model for the right-to-die.
At the other extreme is the medical model for end-of-life choices.   

    The suicide-model right-to-die begins with the fact
that everyone owns his or her life,
which includes the right to end that life.

    If we base the right-to-die on affirming the right to commit suicide,
we seek to make certain that the person really wants to die.
Any convenient means of bringing death might be employed.
The reasons for choosing death might not appear on any medical chart.
But care must be taken to protect any helpers from being charged
with assisting or encouraging an irrational suicide.
Helping someone to choose a foolish death is still a crime
even where suicide itself has been decriminalized.

    If we base end-of-life choices firmly within the practice of medicine,
then death will be chosen with the knowledge and cooperation of doctors.
The reasons for choosing death will be intelligible to doctors.
For example, if we are dying from incurable cancer,
we might choose to shorten the process of dying.

    Logically, the suicide-model right-to-die
has the most direct conflict with everyone who wants to prevent suicide.
Advocates of the right to commit suicide
set themselves directly at odds with all efforts to prevent suicide.

    But medical-model care can cooperate with suicide prevention
because the aim of the medical model end-of-life care
is to affirm and preserve wise medical choices at the end of life.

    Holland exemplifies medical model end-of-life care:
Only doctors (not nurses or technicians or laypersons)
are authorized to assist patients in choosing death.
These chosen deaths follow strict controls and reporting requirements.
And assisting an irrational suicide is still a punishable crime in Holland.

     The book you are reading falls mostly into the medical model
for achieving wise end-of-life medical choices.
The person for whom terminal choices are made is always a
"patient".
Fulfilling the proposed safeguards resembles keeping medical records.
All end-of-life choosing is open and above-board
not secret and hidden.

    The concept 'physician-assisted suicide' is deeply confusing
because it combines the medical model (referring to the doctor)
with forms of human behavior —'suicide'—seldom occurring in hospitals.
Chapter 15 gives a critique of this concept and offers alternatives.

    Efforts to prevent suicide are not at odds with the medical model.
Suicide-prevention can join hands with medical model end-of-life care.



Created March 4, 2012; Revised 3-25-2012; 9-11-2012; 1-26-2013; 3-1-2013; 6-1-2013; 6-19-2013;
7-16-2014; 10-8-2014; 5-21-2015; 8-9-2018; 1-22-2019; 6-11-2020


These two pages are the beginning words of 
How to Die: Safeguards for Life-Ending Decisions.



If you would like to read more about the differences
between the suicide-model right-to-die
and medical model end-of-life care,
 click here.


Go to the beginning of this website
James Leonard Park—Free Library